CHAPTER 51.ELEMENTS AND COMPOUNDS.

Our inquiry must now turn to a new doctrine, which may be called factorial analysis. This doctrine is to some extent an offshoot of that of opposition, and interesting for its own sake. Its essential value, however, is to prepare us for the investigation of modal induction, although some information of relevance to deduction is to be found in it. This doctrine is new, because modal logic involves a lot more forms than the traditional logic, and so an issue which was obvious and minor now looms large.

1.Elements and Compounds.

2.Gross Formulas.

3.Oppositions.

4.Double Syllogisms.

5.Complements.

1.Elements and Compounds.

The various categorical propositions,A,E,I,O, and their modal counterparts, were presented as the building blocks or elements of knowledge. Elementary propositions are relatively abstract items of knowledge, which intersect in various combinations.

The conjunctions of two or more such elementary propositions, concerning the same subject and predicate, may be referred to as compounds. A compound is in a sense a unit of information too, although it is expressed by us as a sum of elements. Knowledge could conceivably have been constructed by giving each compound a distinct form, but then the elements of data they contain in common would have remained hidden. We wisely, even if instinctively, chose to limit the number of forms in our thoughts, and deal with compounds in terms of their constituent elements.

Not all elementary propositions may be conjoined, of course; some are incompatible, for example ‘AandO‘. Some conjunctions are redundant, as when a proposition is conjoined with another which is in any case implicit in it; for instance,AandItogether mean no more thanAalone. However, some compounds are significant, and our task will now be to identify these.

2.Gross Formulas.

At any given stage in the development of knowledge we may have no or partial or complete information, concerning the relation between a specific subject and predicate pair. The sum of information available may be called a formula. A formula may consist of one or more elementary propositions. The elementary propositions taken individually may all be formulas, if they happen to summarize the state of knowledge at that point. Their combinations in distinct consistent compounds, summing up the known without redundancies, are also possible formulas.

Any information not included in a formula is to be considered unavailable in the context of knowledge; thus a formula must contain all known data concerning the two terms in question.

We will express compound formulas in the briefest way, e.g. ‘AIn‘ signifying ‘AandIn‘, without use of extraneous words or symbols for conjunction; it being understood that propositions so fused concern the same subject and predicate, of course.

This study will concern itself only with plural propositions, although some comments about singulars will be made when useful. This is done for the sake of simplicity and clarity, but also in recognition that science is primarily interested in broad statements, and only incidentally in minutiae.

Within the closed system of actual propositions, that covered effectively by classical logic, only five formulas were conceivable:A,I,E,O, andIO. This in a sense resolves the issue of formulas with regard to extensional modality taken in isolation.

When the other types of modality are introduced, the issue becomes less obvious and more complex. The following table shows methodically what combinations, of the 20 elementary propositions (singulars ignored), can occur consistently and without redundancy. It results that there are a total of 195 distinct formulas, 20 of which are of course elementary, and the rest compounds of up to 4 propositions (75X2 + 79X3 + 21X4).

Note that compounds are expressed in their most compressed form (e.g.AIis included inA). In practise, we do not always compress compound statements; sometimes we prefer to stress an implication. For instances, ‘can never be’ stresses that ‘cannot be’ implies ‘is never’; ‘can sometimes be’ suggests a compound of ‘is sometimes’ and ‘can’.

Table 51.1Consistent Conjunctions of Categoricals.

FORMULA

AnAcAAtApInIcIItIpEnEcEEtEpOnOcOOtOp
AnAnAcAAtApInIcIItIp
AcInAcAAtApInIcIItIp
AcAcAAtApIcIItIp
AInAAtApInIcIItIp
AIcAAtApIcIItIp
AAAtApIItIp
AtInAtApInIcIItIp
AtIcAtApIcIItIp
AtIAtApIItIp
AtAtApItIp
ApInApInIcIItIp
ApIcApIcIItIp
ApIApIItIp
ApItApItIp
ApApIp
InInIcIItIp
IcIcIItIp
IIItIp
ItItIp
IpIp
AcInOpAcAAtApInIcIItIpOp
AcOpAcAAtApIcIItIpOp
AInOpAAtApInIcIItIpOp
AIcOpAAtApIcIItIpOp
AOpAAtApIItIpOp
AtInOpAtApInIcIItIpOp
AtIcOpAtApIcIItIpOp
AtIOpAtApIItIpOp
AtOpAtApItIpOp
ApInOpApInIcIItIpOp
ApIcOpApIcIItIpOp
ApIOpApIItIpOp
ApItOpApItIpOp
ApOpApIpOp
InOpInIcIItIpOp
IcOpIcIItIpOp
IOpIItIpOp
ItOpItIpOp
IpOpIpOp
OpOp
AInOtAAtApInIcIItIpOtOp
AIcOtAAtApIcIItIpOtOp
AOtAAtApIItIpOtOp
AtInOtAtApInIcIItIpOtOp
AtIcOtAtApIcIItIpOtOp
AtIOtAtApIItIpOtOp
AtOtAtApItIpOtOp
ApInOtApInIcIItIpOtOp
ApIcOtApIcIItIpOtOp
ApIOtApIItIpOtOp
ApItOtApItIpOtOp
ApOtApIpOtOp
InOtInIcIItIpOtOp
IcOtIcIItIpOtOp
IOtIItIpOtOp
ItOtItIpOtOp
IpOtIpOtOp
OtOtOp
AtInOAtApInIcIItIpOOtOp
AtIcOAtApIcIItIpOOtOp
AtIOAtApIItIpOOtOp
AtOAtApItIpOOtOp
ApInOApInIcIItIpOOtOp
ApIcOApIcIItIpOOtOp
ApIOApIItIpOOtOp
ApItOApItIpOOtOp
ApOApIpOOtOp
InOInIcIItIpOOtOp
IcOIcIItIpOOtOp
IOIItIpOOtOp
ItOItIpOOtOp
IpOIpOOtOp
OOOtOp
ApInOcApInIcIItIpOcOOtOp
ApIcOcApIcIItIpOcOOtOp
ApIOcApIItIpOcOOtOp
ApItOcApItIpOcOOtOp
ApOcApIpOcOOtOp
InOcInIcIItIpOcOOtOp
IcOcIcIItIpOcOOtOp
IOcIItIpOcOOtOp
ItOcItIpOcOOtOp
IpOcIpOcOOtOp
OcOcOOtOp
InOnInIcIItIpOnOcOOtOp
IcOnIcIItIpOnOcOOtOp
IOnIItIpOnOcOOtOp
ItOnItIpOnOcOOtOp
IpOnIpOnOcOOtOp
OnOnOcOOtOp
AcEpAcAAtApIcIItIpEpOp
AIcEpAAtApIcIItIpEpOp
AEpAAtApIItIpEpOp
AtIcEpAtApIcIItIpEpOp
AtIEpAtApIItIpEpOp
AtEpAtApItIpEpOp
ApIcEpApIcIItIpEpOp
ApIEpApIItIpEpOp
ApItEpApItIpEpOp
ApEpApIpEpOp
IcEpIcIItIpEpOp
IEpIItIpEpOp
ItEpItIpEpOp
IpEpIpEpOp
EpEpOp
AIcEpOtAAtApIcIItIpEpOtOp
AEpOtAAtApIItIpEpOtOp
AtIcEpOtAtApIcIItIpEpOtOp
AtIEpOtAtApIItIpEpOtOp
AtEpOtAtApItIpEpOtOp
ApIcEpOtApIcIItIpEpOtOp
ApIEpOtApIItIpEpOtOp
ApItEpOtApItIpEpOtOp
ApEpOtApIpEpOtOp
IcEpOtIcIItIpEpOtOp
IEpOtIItIpEpOtOp
ItEpOtItIpEpOtOp
IpEpOtIpEpOtOp
EpOtEpOtOp
AtIcEpOAtApIcIItIpEpOOtOp
AtIEpOAtApIItIpEpOOtOp
AtEpOAtApItIpEpOOtOp
ApIcEpOApIcIItIpEpOOtOp
ApIEpOApIItIpEpOOtOp
ApItEpOApItIpEpOOtOp
ApEpOApIpEpOOtOp
IcEpOIcIItIpEpOOtOp
IEpOIItIpEpOOtOp
ItEpOItIpEpOOtOp
IpEpOIpEpOOtOp
EpOEpOOtOp
ApIcEpOcApIcIItIpEpOcOOtOp
ApIEpOcApIItIpEpOcOOtOp
ApItEpOcApItIpEpOcOOtOp
ApEpOcApIpEpOcOOtOp
IcEpOcIcIItIpEpOcOOtOp
IEpOcIItIpEpOcOOtOp
ItEpOcItIpEpOcOOtOp
IpEpOcIpEpOcOOtOp
EpOcEpOcOOtOp
IcEpOnIcIItIpEpOnOcOOtOp
IEpOnIItIpEpOnOcOOtOp
ItEpOnItIpEpOnOcOOtOp
IpEpOnIpEpOnOcOOtOp
EpOnEpOnOcOOtOp
AEtAAtApIItIpEtEpOtOp
AtIEtAtApIItIpEtEpOtOp
AtEtAtApItIpEtEpOtOp
ApIEtApIItIpEtEpOtOp
ApItEtApItIpEtEpOtOp
ApEtApIpEtEpOtOp
IEtIItIpEtEpOtOp
ItEtItIpEtEpOtOp
IpEtIpEtEpOtOp
EtEtEpOtOp
AtIEtOAtApIItIpEtEpOOtOp
AtEtOAtApItIpEtEpOOtOp
ApIEtOApIItIpEtEpOOtOp
ApItEtOApItIpEtEpOOtOp
ApEtOApIpEtEpOOtOp
IEtOIItIpEtEpOOtOp
ItEtOItIpEtEpOOtOp
IpEtOIpEtEpOOtOp
EtOEtEpOOtOp
ApIEtOcApIItIpEtEpOcOOtOp
ApItEtOcApItIpEtEpOcOOtOp
ApEtOcApIpEtEpOcOOtOp
IEtOcIItIpEtEpOcOOtOp
ItEtOcItIpEtEpOcOOtOp
IpEtOcIpEtEpOcOOtOp
EtOcEtEpOcOOtOp
IEtOnIItIpEtEpOnOcOOtOp
ItEtOnItIpEtEpOnOcOOtOp
IpEtOnIpEtEpOnOcOOtOp
EtOnEtEpOnOcOOtOp
AtEAtApItIpEEtEpOOtOp
ApItEApItIpEEtEpOOtOp
ApEApIpEEtEpOOtOp
ItEItIpEEtEpOOtOp
IpEIpEEtEpOOtOp
EEEtEpOOtOp
ApItEOcApItIpEEtEpOcOOtOp
ApEOcApIpEEtEpOcOOtOp
ItEOcItIpEEtEpOcOOtOp
IpEOcIpEEtEpOcOOtOp
EOcEEtEpOcOOtOp
ItEOnItIpEEtEpOnOcOOtOp
IpEOnIpEEtEpOnOcOOtOp
EOnEEtEpOnOcOOtOp
ApEcApIpEcEEtEpOcOOtOp
IpEcIpEcEEtEpOcOOtOp
EcEcEEtEpOcOOtOp
IpEcOnIpEcEEtEpOnOcOOtOp
EcOnEcEEtEpOnOcOOtOp
EnEnEcEEtEpOnOcOOtOp

Note in passing that if we considered either natural or temporal modality as a closed system, we would find ourselves in each case with a total of 49 formulas, 12 of which were elementaries, and the remaining 37 were compounds of up to 4 propositions. Formulas involving actual propositions only are 5 in number, and formulas which mix modality types number 102.

Now although this list of formulas is complete in itself, it will become apparent that it does not in fact exhaust the possible states of knowledge. We shall see that formulas of this kind are gross assertions, which do not clarify all the issues involved.

3.Oppositions.

Once we view a compound as a unit, one complex proposition, we may ask what oppositional relations exist between compounds. Consider, for example, the affirmative compoundsAIn,ApIn,ApI. They may be placed in a hierarchy relative to each other and to the cognate elements, as follows:

Diagram 51.1Hierarchy of Compounds.

Looking at the arrows of subalternation, we see a gradual softening of position, ranging fromAntoIp. There is a continuum of affirmative statements, in which temporal modality could also be inserted. A similar hierarchy may be developed for the analogous negatives. More complex, bipolar compounds also have their inter-oppositions, including many such subalternations.

The contradictory of any compound is a disjunctive proposition, note well; it disjoins the contradictories of the various elements involved, in an ‘and/or’ manner. Thus, for examples:

AInis contradicted by ‘Oand/orEp‘,

ApInis contradicted by ‘Onand/orEp‘,

ApIis contradicted by ‘Onand/orE‘.

IfAInis false, then one ofOorEpOorEpmust be true; each of the latter is by itself only contrary toAIn: it is the disjunction as a whole which is contradictory.

Similarly for all other compounds. Note that some ‘ands’ yield impossible combinations; these are as such automatically eliminated. For example: the contradictory ofApIOcis ‘Onand/orEand/orAt‘, in which any combination ofOnwithAtis rejectable at once, meaning that only the alternatives ‘OnorEOnorEorAtEorAt‘ are viable.

There is no need for us to work out all the interrelationships in advance. The work can be done ad hoc, as specific need arises.

4.Double Syllogisms.

Once we regard a compound proposition as a single whole in its own right, we are enticed to ask whether there are corresponding compound syllogisms. Consider, for example, the closed system of actuals. Here, we have one conjunctive formula, ‘IandO‘; its contradictory is ‘AorE‘, since not-{IandO} means notIand/or notO, which meansEandO(=E) orIandA(=A) orEandA(impossible).

With regard to the conjunctive compound ‘IandO‘. Compound syllogism is impossible in the first figure, since we would need both anAand anEmajor premise with the same terms. It is also impossible in the second figure, since this figure only yields negative conclusions. However, in the third figure, we have the following valid double syllogism, merging3/IAIand3/OAO:

Some M are P and some M are not P,

and All M are S,

therefore, Some S are P and some S are not P.

It must follow that the disjunctive compound ‘AorE‘ (which contradictsIO) also has a valid mood of the syllogism. It must be in the first figure, disjoining1/AAAand1/EAE, so that denial of its conclusion causes denial of its major premise, by reductio ad absurdum to the above one:

All M are P or No M is P,

and All S are M,

therefore, All S are P or No S is P.

This shows that the compoundIO, and its contradictory, have a deductive life of their own. These are the only Aristotelean syllogisms capable of processing compounds.

The same can be done with modal compounds. I will not go into detail but simply give a pair of examples:

Some M can be P and some M can not-be P,

and All M must be S,

therefore, Some S can be P and some S can not-be P.

All M must be P or No M can be P,

and All S must be M,

therefore, All S must be P or No S can be P.

Other quantities and modalities than these can similarly be processed. The reader is encouraged to try and evolve a full list of compound syllogisms, as an exercise, with reference to the full list of compound propositions given earlier. Are there tandems involving triple or quadruple compounds?

5.Complements.

To fully understand how any two terms, S and P, are related, we must know their relations in both directions: from S to P and from P to S. These may be called the front and reverse side of the overall relation. The S-P side alone can only provide us with a ‘flat’ picture of the intersection of the terms; the reality is ‘stereoscopic’, and to express it entirely we need to specify the P-S side as well.

The S to P and P to S relations may be called complementary. The possible complements of any S to P relation are the propositions compatible with its converse. Thus, the doctrine of complements is an offshoot of the doctrines of eduction and opposition.

Consider actual categoricals. Since ‘All/This/Some S are P’ are convertible to ‘Some P are S’ only, the possible complements ofA,R, orI(in S-P), areAorO(in P-S). Since ‘No S is P’ is convertible fully to ‘No P is S’, the latter is the only possible complement of the former. Lastly, sinceGandOare not at all convertible, they are compatible with any ofA,E, orIO, on the reverse side.

Similarly for modals. SinceAn,Rn,In,Ap,Rp,Ip, are all convertible toIponly, their possible complements are all the propositions compatible with this converse, namely any form butEn. ForEn, which converts fully toEn, the only possible complement isEn. Lastly, sinceGn,On,Ep,Gp,Op, are none of them at all convertible, any form may complement them. As with naturals, so with temporals.

Just as we developed a list of possible gross formulas for the S to P relationship, we could additionally work out the compatible P to S gross formulas for each S to P gross formula. This would provide us with more complex, ‘two-way’ gross formulas, yielding a fuller picture of reality than heretofore available.

(If the complement is identical in form to the original proposition, then the relation may be said to be reciprocal; otherwise, it is nonreciprocal. Thus, for instance, if ‘all S are P’ and ‘all P are S’ are both true, the relation of S and P is reciprocal; in contrast,Acomplemented byIOis nonreciprocal.)

Note in passing that we could go a step further, and consider not only P-S relations as complements to S-P, but also relations involving the antitheses of one or both of the terms. In that case, obversion, obverted conversion, conversion by negation, contraposition, inversion, and obverted inversion, all become significant, telling us more about the possible combinations of S and P in all their facets.

To get deeper still, we would perhaps have to take transitives into consideration, looking into their possible conjunctions, as ‘supplements’, on the S-P and P-S sides, and indeed, on every other side.

However, all these complications will be ignored in this treatise.